Sunday 16 March 2014

Evolutionary Psychology: An Essay (including a critically reflective appendix)

Evolutionary Psychology: An Essay

This essay is specially focused to elucidate the ongoing debate around the evolutionary theory and its place in the psychological sciences (not that its uselessness is overly contested, but various critiques have come light continue to present across the years). I hope you guys find this essay engaging and informative! 


...

The Evolution of Man
[http://feministsforchoice.com/wp-content/uploads/2012/05/post-one.jpg]



BEGINNING

In the conclusion of the 19th century English naturalist, Charles Darwin’s On the Origin of Species the following statement appears: "In the distant future I see... [p]sychology... based on a new foundation, that of the necessary acquirement of each mental power and capacity by gradation."[1] Darwin’s assertion prophesied a paradigm shift within the field of psychology – a field governed by a new way of thinking: A cognitive evolutionary revolution. It was thirty years later that William James’ highly influential book, Principles of Psychology, began to take part in such a revolution with the concept of “instincts” focused upon in great depth via the implementation of a theoretical frame of thought perpetuated in the Darwinian fashion.[2] To James 'instincts' referred to "specialized neural circuits that are common to every member of a species and are a product of that species’ evolutionary history"[3] – a contention that actuated that which Darwin proposed thirty years prior to James' publication.

It was Darwin’s 'prophesy' (if you will), and James’ expansion on the evolutionary theory that gave rise to the scientific field of sociobiology. Biomathematician Charles J. Lumsden and sociobiologist Edward O. Wilson described sociobiology as follows: "The systematic study of the biological basis of all forms of social behaviour, including sexual behaviour and parent-offspring interaction, in all kinds of organisms."[4] Australian philosopher Michael Dix expands upon the latter with an example: "[In sociobiology] altruism... arose... because a gene which gives its bearer a tendency to aid genetically close relatives will thereby tend to increase its own frequency of representation in the gene pool."[5] In essence, social behaviour is a product of natural selection and random mutations, and it is the aim of the scientist to explain such behaviour in evolutionary terms.[6]

CULTURAL CRITICISM

Sociobiology however did not escape criticism. For example, after the publication of Edward O. Wilson’s book, Sociobiology: The New Synthesis, accusations of racism and sexism along with other injustices and inequalities were brought forth. Many were not in favour of Wilson’s view of sociobiology due to various assertions of his such as that lthe Western social systems are biologically innate"[7], thereby justifying (in a sense) the injustices that are scattered in society and culture.[8] However, those that favoured the field of sociobiology denied the allegations of the critics "that their science is mere right-wing ideology by another name"[9] and made reference to researchers such as the Russian evolutionary theorist, Peter Kropotkin (1902), who held that in the evolution of a species:

mutual protection... is obtained... [thus leading to] the possibility of attaining old age and    of accumulating experience, the higher intellectual development, and the further growth of sociable habits, [the ability to] secure the maintenance of the species, its extension, and its       further progressive evolution.[10] (p. 155)

This citation is important as a response to criticism due to its proactive approach to the development of society in a macro sense. For example, via use of the evolutionary theory Kropotkin identified the evolution of the group due to mutual interpersonal protection, thereby providing the critics with a biological-theoretical foundation of social development. That is, however a society plays out is in accordance with the evolution of the social behaviour of individuals, and inequality as a sub-structure in society may merely be a by-product of the society.

MODULES

John B. Watson in his behaviourist tradition[11] aimed to take the evolutionary theory even further than James, applying it to the psychology of all human behaviour. Watson attempted to separate psychology from its philosophical foundations by eliminating the concept of the mind, and attempting to understand the human being only in terms of what is actually observable.[12] Watson disagreed with James’ contention regarding the 'instincts' within an organism, arguing that behavioural patterns were learned rather than inherited.[13]

The American psychologist Leda Cosmides and her anthropologist husband, John Tooby listed five principles that attempt to establish evolutionary psychology not as a separate field within psychology – such as cognition and personality – but rather as a theoretical basis that could be applied to any point of focus within the psychological field.[14] Where evolutionary psychology differs[15] to James and Watson’s sociobiology is that "evolutionary explanations of human behaviour will not suffice"[16]more is needed. For example, rather than a rigid biological foundation to human psychology as a whole focus, one would benefit – an evolutionary psychologist would argue – in inquiry with light to a 'mental module' outlook. That is, the human mind has engrained within it mental modules with specialized designs.[17] These modules function like a computer, and experts argue that it is via a modular interaction with the world that various phenomena can be understood in greater evolutionary detail.[18]

PRINCIPLES

Before I concentrate on Cosmides and Tooby’s five principles identified within evolutionary psychology I shall clarify what is meant by evolutionary psychology. American Professor of Philosophy Lawrence Shapiro notes that evolutionary psychology focuses on human psychology as a product of evolution via natural selection and "the mechanisms of genetics".[19] In an evolutionary sense, the human mind consists of thousands of "domain-specific modules that arose during the Pleistocene epoch" (i.e. roughly 2,588,000 to 11,700 years ago).[20] These domain-specific modules are comparable to a Swiss army knife – that is, as mentioned previously, different modules are constrained to different behaviours and areas of the mind such as cognition, perception, and so on.[21] These domain-specific modules, notes English philosopher and research professor Simon Blackburn, are responsible for language development, parental motivations, love and friendship, morality, and also emotions.[22] Cosmides and Tooby argue that evolutionary psychology aims to:

...discover and understand the design of the human mind... [with] the mind... [said to be] a      set of information-processing machines that were designed by natural selection to solve adaptive problems faced by our hunter-gatherer ancestors.[23]

In Cosmides and Tooby’s principles of evolutionary psychology it is argued that the human brain should be understood as a physical system whose ways of operating are governed wholly by the laws of physics and chemistry (Principle 1). Principle 2 states that natural selection[24] was responsible for the compilation of our neural circuits in order to solve problems faced by our ancestors during our species’ evolutionary history. Furthermore, perceptive consciousness is not all there is, but our conscious experience and “mind” is the outcome of the extremely complicated operations of our neural circuitry (Principle 3). Principle 4 states that our brains neural circuitry are functionally specialised in order to allow us to solve various adaptive problems (for example, the use of our perceptive processes and discernment of sensory stimuli in order to avoid an oncoming vehicle or collision).

Finally, Cosmides and Tooby assert that ‘[o]ur modern skulls house a stone age mind.’ According to this theory – and as previously noted – the human mind remains in the Pleistocene era because of the intricate status[25] of the evolutionary process of natural selection. Evolutionary psychologists argue that the various domain-specific “mind modules” adapted via the processes of evolution and natural selection, and could have only taken place in an ideal environment of evolutionary adaptedness (or EEA).[26] Up until the Pleistocene epoch this EEA was not considered a fixed place or time, but rather a changing biotic, climatic, geological, and social environment that affected the organisms survival.[27] This environment or set of environments is a crucial tenet in the field of evolutionary psychology, and without it proper understanding of the human mind theorists may argue would be at most superficial.[28] However, these principles within the field of evolutionary psychology have not gone without criticism – as one would doubtless expect in a scientific context.

FURTHER CRITICISM

The late American evolutionary biologist Stephen J. Gould argued that the crucial principle of EEA within evolutionary psychology has no way of being empirically tested, but is only the subject of speculation.[29] Shapiro also notes a number of critics have postulated that there is no way the EEA could have produced such a variety of domain-specific psychological modules due to its intense instability.[30] Also, according to neurosurgery expert Richard W. Byrne and Professor of Evolutionary and Developmental Psychology Andrew Whiten, many of the selection pressures evident in social living and that are most important in the shaping of the human mind are quite changeable, thereby ‘not pressures to which our ancestors could have evolved adaptations.’[31] One final criticism towards evolutionary psychology notes that there is a need for a universal psychology in order to understand human beings: A collective human nature.[32] This problem is due to the fact that humans are highly variable in their psychological makeup with a plethora of cultural and personal differences that the field of evolutionary psychology has ‘barely scratched the surface’ of explaining.[33] Emotional intelligence, cognitive abilities, motivations among a plethora of other abilities, constitute an individual’s psychology, therefore if individuals exhibit differences in the latter they differ psychologically ‘regardless of whether they share domain specific modules.’[34] Therefore, although the evolutionary approach to make sense of human behaviour and psychology may be influential in the explanation of many things (if not all things) in the psychological field, it is evident that strong criticisms that have not yet been adequately responded to (as presented previously) do arise.

END NOTES AND CONCLUSION

This essay has described the theoretical origins of the contemporary psychological approach to understanding the human mind and behaviour – that is: Evolutionary psychology. Its Darwinian roots have been outlined, and its predecessor (sociobiology) brought to light. Theorists in the evolutionary tradition such as John B. Watson have been identified, with more contemporary scholarship also brought to light. Also, various intellectual and theoretical barriers to a number of aspects within evolutionary psychology: The inability of empirical testing of EEA, unlikelihood of various evolved adaptions, and the limitation of the argument for a universal psychology. Overall, it was observed that although evolutionary psychology may be beneficial in order to understand the human mind in evolutionary terms, it is not without limitations that have yet to be empirically explained.

 ...

 Critically Reflective Appendix

The aim of this essay was to explain the evolutionary theory as it applies to the discipline of psychology. I chose to begin with the propagator of the evolutionary theory, Charles Darwin (1859), in order to shed some light onto the thoughts he had in terms of where he saw the field of psychology going in the distant future. Further, sociobiology was chosen to highlight a precession to the field of evolutionary psychology, and critically examined in terms of its contrasts to the latter discipline.

This insight with regards to the origin and development of the evolutionary theory (from Darwin, to James, Wilson, and others) as it applies to psychology was beneficial when introducing the main principles of evolutionary psychology, as presented by Cosmides and Tooby (1997). These principles revealed the central tenets and assumptions of the evolutionary psychology theory, and provided foundational knowledge which was to later be critically examined.

Further – and rather than dismantling all five principles of evolutionary psychology – I chose to focus on three limitations which were evident in this discipline; the inability to empirically test the vastly important principle of EEA, the changeability of very important selection pressures which result in evolved adaptions within an individual, and the flawed belief of a universal psychology among human beings. These limitations have yet to be adequately dealt with, and therefore present stumbling blocks within the field of evolutionary psychology.

Collectively, with the origins, theorists (both contemporary and classic), and the limitations of evolutionary psychology discussed, I have presented a thoroughly evidenced, conspicuously argued essay towards the importance of the evolutionary theory as it relates to contemporary psychology. One would do well to read this essay in order to receive an introductory understanding of the theory as it applies to this discipline, and be enlightened towards the main limitations and advantages.




[1] Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species, W. Clowes and Sons, London, 1859, p. 488.
[2] Leda Cosmides & John Tooby, Evolutionary psychology: A primer, Center for Evolutionary Psychology, California, 1997, http://www.psych.ucsb.edu/research/cep/primer.html, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[3] Ibid.
[4] Charles J. Lumsden & Edward O. Wilson, Genes, mind and culture, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1981.
[5] Michael Dix, Topic 10: Sociobiology, “evolutionary psychology”, and their critics, Lecture notes, Swinburne University of Technology, Melbourne, 2011.
[6] The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Social biology, 1999a, http://www.credoreference.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/entry.do?id=830463, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[7] Ibid.
[8] See 5.
[9] The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Social biology, 1999a, http://www.credoreference.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/entry.do?id=830463, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[10] Peter Kropotkin, Mutual evolution: A factor in evolution, The Anarchist Library, 1902, http://files.uniteddiversity.com/More_Books_and_Reports/The_Anarchist_Library/Petr_Kropotkin__Mutual_Aid__A_Factor_of_Evolution_a4.pdf, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[11] Watson believed that the psychology of a person is in essence what can be observed. He paid little attention to what cannot be observed overtly (such as cognition), considering such things “unscientific”.
[12] Peter J. Bowler, The earth encompassed: A history of the environmental sciences, Norton & Company Ltd., New York, 1992, p. 484.
[13] Ibid.
[14] Refer to 2.
[15] It is important to make a distinction between sociobiology and evolutionary psychology. They latter are two separate approaches that both incorporate the evolutionary theory in order to make sense of behaviour, though sociobiology came about earlier.
[16] The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy, Evolutionary psychology, 1999b, http://www.credoreference.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/entry.do?id=827571, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[17] Mental modules may include one specialized unit for cognition, another for personality, and so on.
[18] Refer to 5; and Steven Pinker, “The two Steves” – Pinker vs. Rose – A debate (Part 1), Edge Foundation, 1998, http://www.edge.org/3rd_culture/pinker_rose/pinker_rose_p1.html, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[19] Lawrence Shapiro, Evolutionary psychology, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London: Routledge, 2009a, http://www.rep.routledge.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/article/Q133?ssid=398194916&n=1&authstatuscode=200, Viewed 1 November 2011; and Steven Rose, Part a. Why do we behave the way we do?, Australian Broadcasting Corporation, 2000, http://www.abc.net.au/science/descent/trans1a.htm, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[20] Ibid.
[21] Refer to 16.
[22] Simon Blackburn, Evolutionary psychology, The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy, 2008, http://www.oxfordreference.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/views/ENTRY.html?entry=t98.e1170&srn=1&ssid=1144557313&authstatuscode=202#FIRSTHIT, Viewed 1 November 2011.
[23] Refer to 2.
[24] Natural selection refers to the evolutionary mechanism proposed by Darwin where gradual changes in an organism take place. Better adapted organisms produce more environmentally adjusted young, and selection occurs when characteristics beneficial to the organism are passed onto offspring. This mechanism within evolution allows for individual differences between organisms in a certain population, and arises through mutation (change within an organism), among other genetic events. Refer to Collins Dictionary of Biology, Natural selection, Collins, London, United Kingdom, http://www.credoreference.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/entry/collinsbiology/natural_selection, Viewed 11 July 2012.
[25] As natural selection takes generations of gradation in order to notice viable differences in an organism, evolutionary psychology argues that not enough generations have passed, and therefore the human mind and circuits within have not developed to their optimum in order to operate in our present post-industrial life – hence the “present” Pleistocene status. Refer to 2.
[26] Ibid.
[27] Refer to 19.
[28] This is due to the importance of understanding the environment in which the brain developed, because without a proper context to build from the essence of understanding the human mind and properties within can be lost.
[29] This may mean, Shapiro notes, that ‘there is no possible test that could be performed to distinguish between two competing hypotheses’, thereby not allowing for falsification and bringing to light the unscientific nature of the EEA. However, it is wise to note that these accusations for the unscientific nature of the EEA are ambiguous at best. Refer to: Stephen J. Gould, Evolution: The pleasures of pluralism, The New York Review of Books, New York, 1997, http://philoscience.unibe.ch/documents/TexteFS10/Gould1997b.pdf Viewed 1 November 2011; and Lawrence Shapiro, Criticisms of evolutionary psychology, Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, London: Routledge, 2009b, http://www.rep.routledge.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/article/Q133SECT3, Viewed 1 November 2011. Also, American experts in the field of evolutionary psychology, Elsa Ermer, Leda Cosmides, and John Tooby note that if the researcher is unable to attain a proper understanding of an environment that evolutionary change has occurred in, this presents us with a problem of not understanding the domain-specific modules arising therein. In essence, clueless environments produce clueless mechanisms. Refer to Steven W. Gangestad & Jeffry A. Simpson (eds.), Evolution of mind: Fundamental questions and controversies, Guilford Press, New York, 2007, p. 157-158.
[30] Ibid.
[31] Richard W. Byrne and Andrew Whiten cited in 29. Byrne and Whiten refer to the Machiavellian intelligence theory (an approach that makes use of an alleged personality trait in which a person merits a gain at the expense of another. One’s ‘social conduct strategy’ cares little of where others may seem to be at a disadvantage, as long as he or she stands to gain via manipulation or the person or situation) in order to explain how an organism tends to benefit in society given certain selection pressures that are quite changeable and not pressures that would have applied to our ancestors. Refer to Elsevier’s Dictionary of Psychological Theories, Machiavellian theory, Elsevier Science and Technology, Oxford, United Kingdom, 2006, http://www.credoreference.com.ezproxy.lib.swin.edu.au/entry/estpsyctheory/machiavellian_theory, Viewed 12 July 2012.
[32] Refer to 29.
[33] Jamie C. Confer, Judith A. Easton, Diana S. Fleischman, Cari D. Goetz, David M.G. Lewis, Carin Perilloux & David M. Buss, Evolutionary psychology: Controversies, questions, prospects and limitations, American Psychologist, vol. 65, no. 2, 2010, p. 110-126, p. 122-3.
[34] Ibid.

No comments:

Post a Comment